In the West, the word "meditation" has a long and
complicated history, and it has no exact counterpart in Asian cultures.
However, interactions with Asian, especially Indian, spiritual traditions have
had a significant impact on modern use of the language. As a result, our
present perception of the definition represents a combination of Western and
Asian interests. The word "meditation," mostly in its Latin form
meditatio, has long been associated with Christianity in the West, but it has
often been associated with philosophy and the arts. In this multifaceted
tradition, the word usually refers to an associative and nonlinear form of
reflection that goes beyond strictly logical reasoning but still “engages the
analytical or discursive faculties,” as the Oxford English Dictionary puts it. Meditation is a form of meditation, prayer, or creative visualization
that is often based on scripture. When Western writers started to read Indian
and other Asian classics, the word "meditation" came to be used in a
broader context, referring to Buddhist and Yogic rituals that are "aimed
at the eradication of rational or earthly mental thought," according to
the Oxford English Dictionary. The technological direction of the empirical
investigation of these activities has bolstered certain non-discursive interpretations
of the word.
Almost all empirical meditation research explores technical,
rather than content-oriented, Asian activities, as Are Holen points out in this
volume, and these have often dominated the general public's interest in
meditation over the last half-century. As a consequence, the word
"meditation" is now most often used to describe activities that do
not primarily include "the intellectual or discursive faculties." The
Asian rituals examined in this book include a wide range of beliefs, including
discursive and non-discursive practices, content-oriented and narrowly
technological practices. The current essay seeks to describe the word
"meditation" in a way that raises interesting concerns about the
essence of meditation as a starting point for these discussions. Meditation is
an attention-based method for inner change, according to the proposed meaning.
This description is expansive and inclusive, but it is also very progressive in
certain ways. In the one side, it encompasses a variety of rituals that are
frequently referred to by other names, such as ceremony, meditation, and
reflection. However, it specifically prohibits a variety of activities that are
often referred to as meditation, such as pure calming methods.
Furthermore, the proposed term is limited to technical practices
and excludes randomly produced mental states. It also excludes literary or
metaphysical works that are often referred to as "meditations" on a
particular subject. The different aspects of the concept of "meditation,"
as well as the boundaries between meditation and other phenomena, will be
discussed in depth in this article. Furthermore, by connecting these elements
to the tradition of meditation on the Eurasian plateau, as well as material
from other essays in this book, this essay would seek to demonstrate the
definition's cultural significance.
However, certain fundamental definitional issues must be
discussed before proceeding with this discussion. Definitions that are generic
Some cultural historians object to the use of abstract, unitary meanings, such
as the one that defines meditation as "an attention-based strategy for
inner change," since they are intentionally disrespectful to cultural and
historical features in some ways. In comparison to the historical, cultural,
and social “situatedness” reflected here, such a description of meditation can
easily be accused of being anachronistic and Eurocentric in application of
modern-day Western ideas on a largely premodern Asian material. This is easily mistaken for what cultural theorists
derisively refer to as "essentialism," a way of thought that ascribes
a stable and frequently abstract "essence" to social, cultural, or
otherwise human phenomena. As a result, generic meanings are often used as
instruments by natural scientists, who appear to ignore cultural and historical
differences and regard individual vocabulary usage and local semantic schemes
as having no bearing on their study.
Indeed, scientists engaged in scientific science or
psychology proposed the majority of earlier standardized concepts of
meditation. Furthermore, while generic meanings resist making overt references
to cultural and historical aspects, they are far from benign in the sense that
they are unaffected by their surroundings. The above-mentioned concept of
meditation is related to scientific concerns, which are often rooted in culture
and tradition. Some may argue that the definition's reference to
"technique" reflects a strong Asian influence, whereas European and
Middle Eastern forms of meditation are often less technical and more devotional
than many Indian and Chinese forms, while others may argue that the reference
to "technique" is a result of modern scientific and technological
concerns and therefore in reality linked to "technique." Both ideas
can include some facts.
The idea that a definition's semantic ramifications are
bound to embody certain cultural and historical considerations clearly means
that these concerns should be explained and made the subject of critical
reflection, which is exactly what this essay aims to do. Our meaning refers to
certain characteristics of a "stuff" called "meditation"
that can, for the time being, be considered useful and fascinating to
investigate and debate. In any case, it's unclear what will be an alternative
to a standardized description. We should not "rest satisfied with reproducing native
lexicography and, thus, giving in to the prevailing culture of localism,
calling any attempt at generalization a western imposition," as religion
historian Jonathan Z. Smith puts it. The formal stipulative and precising
processes by which the academy challenges and attempts to regulate
second-order, specialist use cannot be substituted for how ‘they' use a word.”
It would be difficult to see what a comparative analysis of
meditation would compare if it was exclusively focused on local ideas rather
than a philosophy of meditation that transcends all languages and cultures. The
problem does not seem to be solved by Smith's own proposal of a
"self-consciously polythetic mode of classification that surrenders the
concept of ideal, special, single differentia." “No examples of attempts
at the polythetic classification of religions or religious phenomena,” Smith
says, and a critic of Smith's work observes that “the reader who wants an
exhaustive list of the features of a polythetic concept of faith is in for a
disappointment; Smith does not provide it.”
Though subsequent scholars have made a few attempts in this
direction, the task has largely proved to be too difficult. Polythetic
definitions have proven useful in biology, where they have aided in the
resolution of issues left by conventional monothetic species definitions. Also
polythetic meanings, in such situations, have a monothetic heart, since they
presuppose a single ancestral history of species listed together. Meditation,
as a social and personal phenomenon, has no such monothetic core—no stable
"essence," if you will.
Furthermore, whereas biological organisms are typically
defined by features that have “a actual, distinct, and independent character,”
meanings of social and personal phenomena “cannot be carried out by comparison
to discrete empirical particulars, but require instead a dependence on further
features of the same character that are equally polythetic,” as Rodney Needham
puts it. Since “comparative research, whether morphological, practical, or
mathematical, are made more difficult and perhaps even unfeasible,” the
enormous difficulty of polythetic classification of social and personal phenomena
can ultimately make it impracticable.
There's no need to believe that social and personal
manifestations like meditation, which lack the monothetic essence found in
biological organisms, are naturally separated into groups. More than likely,
they are not natural taxa, and any grouping, beyond the conceptualizations
imposed on them by various languages in various ways, would include artificial
elements. The aim of describing meditation is to provide a single point of
reference to which comparative studies of meditation may relate, rather than to
imply a natural class of meditative phenomena.
A monothetic definition fits this purpose better than a
polythetic definition since it is more concise and less ambiguous, which is why
some scholars have considered it "fair to question if a definition of a
polythetic term is at all a definition, because it is obviously
imprecise." Despite accusations to the contrary, a precise generalized
meaning can easily be paired with a keen understanding of the historical and
cultural situatedness of natural language meanings, as well as the social and
personal realities to which those definitions relate, as well as the
ambiguities, family resemblances, overlaps, and gradient distinctions that
underpin both language and fact.
Natural language terms like “meditation” in English—or, for
that matter, the Arabic dhikr, Sanskrit dhyana, and Chinese jng-zu—are
multivalent, mutable, and fuzzy, much like the social and personal phenomenon
to which they refer. Ses ideas and phenomena, on the other hand, can all be
usefully linked to a single meaning of meditation, even though they differ in
different ways. If meditation is characterized as a practice, the states of
mind protected by the English term “meditation” and the Sanskrit dhyana, as
well as the metaphysical and creative items referred to by the English term,
fall beyond the meaning. However, the recitation implied by Arabic dhikr, the imagery
implied by some Tantric applications of Sanskrit dhyana, and the seated pose
implied by Chinese jng-zu limit these terms to a much narrower variety of
activities than our common understanding of meditation. A monothetic meaning
provides one with a shared emphasis in a comparative analysis of meditation,
against which the peculiarities of each practice can be illuminated. Just like thinking about dhikr as meditation helps one
understand the practice better, examining meditation in the light of
presumptions coming from dhikr highlights meditation's connection to modern
forms of human subjectivity that are ingrained in the way we think and act but
are not often easily thinking of their similarities and differences is a great
way to learn more about all of them.
Bashir uses the phrase "with its most commonsensical
English sense," but his argument is equally true if we think of meditation
as a technical concept with a single definition. A rudimentary version of a generalized
meaning would be purely stipulative, with no broader analytical ambitions than
to have a common ground for the comparative treatment of similar phenomena
through cultures and languages A theoretical definition is a more powerful variant of a generalized
definition, as it not only has functional ramifications but also aims to link
the given notion to broader theoretical problems. As we've seen, describing
meditation as a method rather than a state or a nontechnical mode of activity
suggests a certain theoretical understanding of meditation, as does the idea of
meditation being attention-based, excluding automatized ritualistic practice,
and performed in order to achieve long-term inner transformation rather than
only passing changes of state or changes that only impact the body.
Because of these metaphysical consequences, a consideration
of the concept becomes much more than a mere terminological problem, since it
touches on the essence of the phenomenon to which the word in question refers.
Methodology Both ways of meditation, according to our meaning, are
“techniques.” Unlike many of the ordinary social interactions usually observed
by sociologists and anthropologists, a method is a deliberate procedure that is
not taken for granted. A technique is formal in the sense that its methods are
well-defined; however, this does not rule out the possibility of accidental or
even imaginative components, such as when unexpected thoughts are the focus of
meditation. It is continuous, as in the sequence of postures and movements
involved in Hatha Yoga or Tàij, the nonrepetitive chanting of the whole Lotus
Stra in Buddhism or the Book of Psalms, not sequential, as in the sequence of
postures and movements involved in Hatha Yoga or Tàij, the nonrepetitive
chanting of the entire Lotus Stra in Buddhism or the Book of Psalms.
A technique is separated from other practices in terms of
time, stance, and place, as well as by particular routines. And it's being done
to produce such outcomes, which we'll get to later, at least in part by using
fundamental processes that are implicit in the essence of the human body and
mind. The technical elements of meditation are seen with ambivalence in many
meditative practices. For example, content-oriented meditative prayer and
imagery are common, devotional rituals emphasize an intimate relationship with
God, and apophatic practices traditionally emphasize “unmediated” interaction
with the divine or “direct” realization of ultimate reality. In both
situations, this will lead to a pessimistic outlook about meditation's
technicality. This does not mean that content-oriented, devotional, or
apophatic rituals are not included in our definition; however, we put a greater
focus on their technical elements, as opposed to the traditions' emphases. The
ambivalence about the technicality of meditation is often expressed directly in
paradoxical comments, such as Meister Eckhart's notion of a "pathless
direction" in the thirteenth to fourteenth centuries, or the Zen Buddhist
notion of a "gateless gate."
At other moments, a deep cynicism about meditative methods
is juxtaposed with exhortations to meditate, such as when the “Platform Stra”
portrays Hunéng, a seventh- to eighth-century Chinese Zen master, as saying
that he “has no techniques,” w jling, but in the same work exhorting his
disciples to continue practicing “straight sitting,” dun-zu, i.e., meditation,
after he has passed The paradox is simply explained in “The Epistle of Prayer”
in the Christian context: “It is not necessary for a man to achieve greatness
in this work unless these two ways, or two others like them, come first.” The
perfection of this piece, though, is its suddenness, which comes without
means.” Jiddu Krishnamurti is best known in modern times for his resistance to
meditation practices, claiming that "the reality is a pathless
forest," but others have interpreted his stance as a method of formal
meditative awareness training. A recent series of essays on the Zen tradition
of shi-kan ta-za, or "only stay," alternates between insisting on the
technique's lack of method and explaining distinctly technical elements
including exposure to the lower belly, precise breathing techniques, and a
heavy emphasis on proper bodily posture.
Sheng Yen, a Buddhist master from Taiwan, calls one of his
meditation methods "the method of no method." The deep
goal-orientation implicit in the concept of a technique is one explanation for
this doubt or ambivalence. Techniques are used to achieve specific effects, but
actively pursuing effects can, paradoxically, make achieving them more challenging.
The achievement of a target may divert the mind's attention away from the
actual practice, and it may include a mental concentration so intense that it
fails to notice facts that are more transient and ephemeral.
A technological mindset can also inspire passivity, as
though the transformative effects of meditation would happen on their own,
almost mechanically or magically, rather than requiring a deep sense of agency
and personal involvement. It may also obstruct the personal dedication expected
in some meditative rituals, such as the Sikh practices discussed in this volume
by Kristina Myrvold. In the Christian tradition, relying on tactics is often
seen as impeding God's grace, as in the following quote from Jacques Philippe's
Time for God about meditative prayer: “St. Jane Frances de Chantal once said,
‘The safest way of prayer is not to have one, because prayer is received not by
artifice,' as we might think now, but by grace.' There is no such thing as a ‘method' of prayer, as in a
series of directions or protocols that we must simply follow in order to pray
effectively.” In general, meditation's technological orientation can be
compared with prayer's content-oriented orientation. Although both meditation
and prayer seek to achieve such results, prayer usually does so explicitly
through its text, while meditation usually does so indirectly, in a nonlinear
manner, through technological elements that draw on universal mechanisms.
For instance, prayer may aim at obtaining the forgiveness of
sins by asking for it, or may try to achieve intimate contact with God through
the expression of devotion, while meditation may seek to obtain its
transformative effects at least partly by means of cross-cultural elements that
go beyond such content, for example, by directing one’s attention to the
breath, by repeating certain sound combinations, by gazing at or visualizing
geometrical figures, and so on. Such mechanisms typically lie beyond the
individual’s direct control, and the main effects of meditation result from the
methodical practice of a technique rather than any purposeful striving.
Though the result of prayer can often be out of one's reach,
it is usually thought of as relying on God's grace rather than any processes
found in the human mind or body. Also technological elements are given
content-oriented meanings in many cultures, such as when the breath is
interpreted as an indicator of existence's transience in Buddhist contexts, as
a connection to celestial energies in Daoist and Yogic contexts, or as the breath
of life in Christian contexts. And from the viewpoint of an observer will the
universal processes involved in certain elements be seen, regardless of the
cultural context in which they are used. Since this makes it easier to quantify, scientific concepts
of meditation prefer to focus on its theoretical dimensions. Meditation makes
“use of a particular procedure, precisely defined,” according to one often
cited term. Instead of or in addition to "technique," other meanings
include terminology like "psychoactive workout," "social
conditioning," and "self-regulation/emotional and attentional
regulatory practice." Meditation's technical orientation is often compared
with other practices' material orientation by stating that meditation stresses
"method rather than content," whereas non-meditative practices like
self-hypnosis, imagination, and psychotherapy "primarily aim at
transforming mental contents such as feelings, images, and emotions."
However, in our definition, substantive material is not
removed from the concept of meditation as long as technical elements are
present. The activity orientation involved in describing meditation as a
technique includes a vital component of individual organization. Meditation is
something that the professional does, not something that is administered to him
or her. Our meaning excludes so-called accidental or natural
meditations, which occur as unintentional reactions to a scene or circumstance,
such as the Buddha's well-known childhood experience of meditative bliss: “I
remember once, when my father the Sakyan was working and I was seated in the
cool shade of a rose-apple tree, I entered & stayed in the first jhana
=Skt. dhyana; generally translated as “meditation”: rapture & relaxation
born of seclusion, followed by guided reflection & evaluation.”
Most traditions, however, recognize that meditative activity
often takes place in a setting, and that elements of the context can be as
significant as the mediation technique itself in causing transformative
transformation, as Sarah Shaw argues in this volume for the Buddhist example.
Person or communal meditation can be practiced, and even communal meditation
can require a lot of individual agency, as shown by the fact that monks who
have been practicing meditation together for years don't really know what each
other is doing.
The degree of reliance on an instructor or master can also
differ, ranging from no reliance beyond initial guidance to so-called
supervised meditations, in which all stages of the practice depend on
continuous directions from a teacher or a tape recorder, as in some of the Sikh
practices mentioned in this volume by Myrvold. The master's position in Morten
Schlütter's kan activities is an in-between scenario, in which the meditator is
repeatedly given new kans to ponder in addition to the original technical
guidance. Pay close attention. Meditation is founded on the utilization
of focus, according to the proposed meaning. In one way, this is stating the
obvious: all ways of meditation include focusing one's mind on a single
meditation object. The object may be a static object, like a geometrical figure
in yantra meditation, or a dynamic aspect, like the ever-changing truth sought
to be included in shi-kan ta-za and other Zen practices.
In any case, the approach entails drawing the viewer's focus
to this thing. Meditation entails cultivating the mode of attention in addition
to the focus of attention. Although many meditative practices have detailed discussions
of what constitutes an effective meditation object, others argue that any
external or internal object may serve this purpose, with the key distinction
being the mode of focus, mental orientation, and how attention is focused
toward this object. In certain instances, this entails the development of a
single-minded, deeply absorbed, and effortless mental state. In other ways, the teaching aims to develop an open and
accommodating mental approach toward sudden desires and even distracting
feelings. In order to overcome worldly connection and let the mind reside in a
realm that goes beyond all matters, meditative attitudes are often seen as
stimulating an aspect of alienation or separation from the artefacts of the
universe. Meditation is thought to promote a way of life that brings in a
deeper intimacy with the stuff of the world at all moments, or perhaps even
concurrently.
In any situation, the mode of focus is crucial, and every
effort to meditate mechanically, on autopilot, would be outside of our meaning.
Meditation is a technique for increasing one's consciousness. Meditation
methods, according to a number of theoretical definitions, include the
preparation of consciousness, or perception. Some of them also go so far as to
exclude visualization exercises from the area of meditation, claiming that they
seek to change the contents of attention rather than train the attention
itself. They also exempt “controlled breathing and body postures,
yoga, or body movement and assumed energy modulation, Tai Chi Tài-j and Chi
gong Q-gng” based on the same rationale. In reality, most types of recitative practice,
which often includes the deliberate modification of mental material, will be
excluded from this line of thought. The effect will be a very limited definition
of meditation, excluding, for example, the visualization methods discussed in
this volume by Madhu Khanna, Geoffrey Samuel, and Sarah Shaw, as well as most
aspects of orthodox Christian meditation.
The irony is that concentration preparation does not
preclude efforts to change or alter the contents of the mind. Most visualization
exercises, as well as many body practices and recitative techniques, combine
the two. In the next post, we'll return to a review of the uses of attention,
which classifies meditation methods in part based on the "center of
attention" and "form of attention." Transformation of the Soul
Meditation is performed with the aim of completing "mental change,"
according to the proposed meaning. Traditional views of the modifications are theological or
metaphysical, but nothing in our meaning precludes psychological,
philosophical, or other existential interpretations. Descriptions of
transformative reform are usually diverse and ambiguous in literary records
from various schools and traditions. There are only a few dispersed comparative
analyses of long-term trajectories of meditative systems in the scientific
literature, and they are narrow in depth.
One scholarly concept of meditation mentions "social
growth," but says nothing on what it entails beyond general comments about
promoting positive feelings and suppressing negative emotions. “Inner
transition results of long-term fundamental changes involving many facets of
the individual, such as perceptual, physical, intellectual, moral, or behavioral
behaviors, gradually bringing about the anchoring of the individual in more
fundamental aspects of existence,” I propose as a preliminary concept. This description can be seen in a number of ways. Such
transition is commonly associated with getting closer to God in monotheistic
religions originating in the Middle East, and the same may be true of the Sikh
tradition of nm simran mentioned by Myrvold in this volume. The aim of many
Hindu schools, including Edwin F. Bryant's Yogic disciplines and Khanna's
yantra and cakra practices, is to understand the supreme Self, purua or tman,
which is also sometimes equated with God, vara or Brahman, or iva in union with
akti.
Though some have pointed to similarities between the
ultimate Self that Buddhism is supposed to deny and the "Buddha
nature," Ch. fó-xng, prevalent in the meditative traditions of Tibet, as
discussed by Samuel in this volume, and of East Asia, as discussed by Samuel in
this volume, the aim in the various Buddhist approaches is either to become
enlightened to the fundamental emptiness of the self or of all being, though
some have pointed to similarities between the ultimate Self that Buddhism is
supposed to deny. The aim of Daoism, as defined by Harold D. Roth, and
Neo-Confucianism, as described by Masaya Mabuchi, is to enhance one's proximity
to the Way, Dào, which has clear moralistic undertones in Neo-Confucianism.
While some of them mean a greater mystical realm to which the meditator
eventually opens his or her eyes, modern schools of meditation frequently
reject the metaphysical connotations of conventional terminologies. Others, as shown by Holen's contribution, have a more
scientific approach to the processes at hand. In both cases, the aim is for the
individual to become more permanently rooted in facets of life that are deemed
more central in the particular cultural sense than his or her starting point.
This perspective on inner change does not imply belief in
the perennialist notion that all schools of meditation, theology, mysticism,
and so on are, at their heart, efforts to achieve the same universal truth, as
Robert K. C. Forman famously claimed in the contemporary sense. In certain
cases, structural and linguistic parallels between different meditative
traditions can represent actual substance similarities, whether that substance
is linked to the notion of an ineffable experience of a non-phenomenal reality,
as is usually argued within the perennialist discourse, or to effable and
phenomenal experiences, as Matthew T. Kapstein suggests for the widespread of
meditative traditions. In other contexts, as with comparisons between descriptions
of meditative and drug-induced spiritual encounters, formal and informative
parallels between various practices can be superficial and gloss over
underlying distinctions. Along with some fundamental variations, the structure
of their discourses binds the different schools of meditation together. “Models
of incremental self-transformation, often based upon the active cultivation
through years of ascesis or meditative practice, and those of abrupt or
sometimes aggressive alteration in the structure of the self—for example, in
religious conversion,” write David Shulman and Guy G. Stroumsa.
The transitions caused by meditative practice seem to be
firmly placed in the first division when stated this way. However, though
meditation is often viewed as a lifelong endeavor, meditative transition is
often viewed as a rapid and, paradoxically, unplanned occurrence. This is
particularly true of the prevalent schools of Zen Buddhism, which Schlütter
describes in this book. Perhaps even more interestingly, that is also true in
certain Christian ways of reflection, as shown by the quote from "The
Epistle of Prayer" quoted above, which indicates that the transformations
are "sudden and without any means."
When Shulman and Stroumsa say that in incremental
self-transformation, the self is "the active agent of its own
evolution," while in abrupt transition, the self is "a passive
beneficiary of the process," the situation becomes much more complicated.
This seems to be fair. However, as previously mentioned, the relationship
between the practices involved in meditative activity and the outcomes obtained
is not linear, regardless of whether the effects are incremental or abrupt.
Shaw observes how “meditation subjects, selected and engaged with intent,
coincide with surprise objects, or external activities, happening at critical
and timely moments” in her essay on southern Buddhism in this book. Suddenness and passive recipiency are mixed with gradualness
and individual agency, or, in Shaw's terms, "a ready openness to the
fortuitous and lucky." The scientific aspects of meditation are mixed with
the nontechnical aspects of daily life. Sudden religious conversion can also be
claimed to imply a person's anchoring of more basic facets of life, at least as
seen through the lens of the faith in question.
However, Shulman and Stroumsa may be correct in claiming
that such conversion is unusual in meditative processes. Meditation is most
commonly practiced within a particular tradition to which the adept already
belongs, and the practice pursues long-term aims established by this tradition,
at least in premodern contexts. Meditation is dependent on social settings as
well as instruction, transmission, and perception cultures, in addition to the
technique itself. It is often performed in groups, and many schools of
meditation claim that the benefits of group meditation outweigh the benefits of
individual meditation. Many meditative practices put considerable power in the
hands of the master disciple, such as the abba of early Christianity, the
shaikh of Sufism, the Indian guru, or the Chinese sh-fu. All of this raises the
issue of what the essence of the transformed "individual" or
"self" is. Is this self, like the nineteenth-century Western idealist
view, essentially a subjective arena of human agency springing from within? Is
it a tabula rasa that gets its key characteristics from experiences and
pressures from the environment, resulting in an interior or interiorized
sociality?
One potential understanding of meditation's deep
incorporation into its sociocultural meaning is that the shifts are the result
of an outside-in movement, in which socially determined perceptions are
interiorized and influence the transition. These standards may be part of the
ritual itself in certain cases, such as meditations on a particular religious
subject, or they may be part of the atmosphere surrounding the practice in
other cases. In either case, this outside-in movement resembles one of
the potential operating processes of the placebo effect in psychology,
neuroscience, and somatic medicine, where optimism and beliefs have been
proposed as key influences in the treatment's outcome. It also has elements in
common with autosuggestion and autohypnosis, all of which would be explored in
more depth in the following article. Finally, it is consistent with social and
cultural constructivist views on human cognition, which have long been dominant
in cultural and religious studies.
However, this isn't the only way to explain how meditation
and its sociocultural meaning are so closely linked. As we've seen, Shulman and
Stroumsa argue that meditative change entails more involved agency, not less,
than abrupt religious conversion. Meditation is sometimes seen as largely an
individual endeavor, except in communal contexts, as argued above. The enhanced
influence due to communal activity in meditation traditions is only partially
attributed to simple social influences such as inspiration and encouragement;
it is most commonly interpreted as the result of divine forces released during meditation. Directed meditations, such as some of the Sikh practices
mentioned by Myrvold in this book, are at best peripheral to the area of
meditation of most religions, in which practice is carried out in direct
response to continuous guidance from a meditation guide, or a tape or compact
disc, as in some of the Sikh practices described by Myrvold in this volume.
Modern scientific conceptions of meditation tend to emphasize human agency,
describing it as a "self-regulation exercise" that employs a
"self-focus capacity" or a "self-observation mentality" to
achieve a "self-induced state."
Furthermore, there is often a conflict between meditative
traditions and the values and ideals engendered by their broader religious or
cultural backgrounds, which meditation is often thought to overcome. The
Chinese Zen “recorded sayings,” y-lù, urge meditators to “destroy the Buddha
when you see him, and kill the patriarchs when you see them,” implying the need
to let go of all inner obedience to sacred authority. The relationship between the established church and its
numerous contemplative orders has been tense in Catholicism, owing to the
contemplatives' insistence on their own personal visions of realities that the
church feels compelled to control. The technological and non-semantic existence
of some meditation objects—such as body and breath practices, “objectless”
concentration training, meaningless mantras, aniconic yantras, de-semanticized
Zen kans, and the blurring of the recitative material in some Sufi dhikr practices—indicates
that meditation can transcend the webs of meaning offered by the cultural and
religious context.
All of this suggests that, rather than just adapting to
societal norms, people are becoming more autonomous. Social contexts can be
more important than only providing external cultural values, moral beliefs, and
interpretive webs of meaning. The environment's inspiration and affirmation do
not actually promote conformism, but they may provide the sense of security
required for individual exploration of existential problems. Similarly, the
instruction of instructors or masters may not only be directed toward the
exercise of authority, but may also aim to offer resources for technological or
existential clarity to the pupil or disciple.
According to this perspective, meditative change entails not
only the interiorization of external perceptions or webs of meaning, but also
the activation of internal and individual cycles that may be physiological,
psychological, or metaphysical in nature, or all three at once. This viewpoint
is consistent with perennialism but does not need it, since the inner elements
stimulated may or may not belong to what is called the perennial “core” of
prayer, mysticism, or faith. In the next essay in this series, we'll look at
how outside-in and inside-out shifts interact in different ways of meditative practice.
Some modes of self-transformation, as described by Shulman
and Stroumsa, do not always mean the long-term anchoring of an individual in
the more fundamental aspects of life that meditative transformation and
religious conversion are thought to imply. Demonic possession and spirit
mediumship may refer to long- or short-term contact with entities that are
outside of most people's daily experience, but they are rarely considered to be
part of the more basic layers of life in the context mentioned above. The most apparent long-term change involved in spirit
mediumship is not on the part of the spirit medium himself, but on the part of
the group or person that the medium is representing. Finally, while madness may
be long-term or short-term, it is generally assumed to cause a person to lose
touch with the fundamentals of daily reality rather than becoming embedded in
more essential facets of life.
Nonetheless, some currents of thought in a variety of
cultures have treated certain types of madness as portals to or expressions of
knowledge or inspiration, and are often also linked to meditative activity.
Though none of these modifications—religious conversion, demonic possession,
spirit mediumship, or insanity—are characteristic of meditation, they do exist,
demonstrating the breadth of the changes associated with the activity. The
qualifier "inner" in the word "inner transition" means that
the modifications are implied to go beyond merely physical effects on the body.
This is in contrast to other medical and gymnastic practices,
in which mental preparation is prioritized over physical accomplishment or
well-being. The common use of physical exercise for character development falls
somewhere in the middle. Both the body and the mind are normally engaged in
meditation, but the “embodied” essence of meditation is not included in its
meaning. Many meditative traditions emphasize the body by postures and
gestures, as well as bodily meditation artefacts and numerous efforts to
"liberate" the mind or spirit from the body. The verb zu "to rest" is a constituent aspect in
many expressions for meditation in Chinese: jng-zu, sit in quietude, d-zu,
hit-sit, chán-zu, sit in zen, zu-chán, sit in zen, ji-f-zu, sit cross-legged,
dun-zu, sit straight, and zhèng-zu, sit straight. While sitting meditation is
the most common form of the practice, there are also lying, standing, walking,
and even dancing meditations. In the same way, though closed eyes are
associated with meditation, half-closed or open eyes are also normal.
And, whatever part the body plays in the practice and method
of meditation, the transformative changes it brings about go beyond bodily
considerations. Mental States Any characteristics often associated with
meditation, such as sitting posture and closed eyes, are not included in our
classification. This is particularly true in the case of so-called meditative
states of mind. These factors have little bearing on the concept, which emphasizes
long-term trait changes rather than short-term state changes.
In this regard, our technical use of the word
"meditation" differs from common English usage, which often refers to
brief shifts in state, often as a result of practice and other times as a
sudden shift with no relation to practice. The Arabic muraqaba, mushhada, and
mu'yana; Sanskrit yoga, dhyana, and samadhi; and Chinese chán, borrowed from
Sanskrit dhyana, all have this semantic discrepancy between activity and state
of mind. In many meditative practices, transient states of mind play
a significant part, and the transient encounters described in the meditative
literature are often understood to be transformative in the sense of redefining
a person's relationship to himself and his surroundings. This holds true for
many of the traditions mentioned in this book, including Bryant's presentation
of the seven ways of samadhi in the Yoga tradition. Meditation is often related
to particular states of mind, and the essence of those transient states may
often separate it from other activities.
Such states are also more easily defined and identified than
long-term changes of trait, and most meditative traditions have terms that
designate states or stages along the way. State-oriented practices are not
excluded from the proposed concept, but they must also be expected to bring in
long-term reforms. Sufism, for example, accepts a number of common intermittent
states, but connects them to a number of long-term phases. Many traditions caution practitioners of the dangers of
temporary states, which may tempt them away from true transformation. Schlütter
explains how the Chinese Zen master Dà-hu criticizes those who want quietness
instead of “breaking their mind of life and death” in his contribution to this
volume. Another Chinese Zen master, X-yn, advises against "greedily
pursuing the domain of purity," which he describes as "a Zen disease
to be avoided by any practitioner."
In the Christian faith, “The Cloud of Unknowing” warnings
against the practitioner wrongly “imagining... to be the fire of love, lighted
and fanned by the power and kindness of the Holy Ghost,” and “The Epistle of
Prayer” urges the practitioner to “neither care nor think whether you are in
pain or in bliss.” In today's world, Jon Kabat-Zinn, the most well-known
adherent of mindfulness meditation, states unequivocally that "every state
of mind is a meditative state," whereas Acem Meditation's free mental
attitude is defined as "neither a thought, nor a specific experience, nor
a state of mind."
The pervasive interest in meditative states of mind reflects
a deep fascination with "experience" that has dominated religious
thought since the late eighteenth century, and contemporary religious studies
since William James' classic book The Varieties of Religious Experience. The
“experience” orientation of religious studies in general, and Asian religion
studies in particular, has been slammed as a new Western concept imposed on
premodern and Asian religions. Modern Hindu and Buddhist adherents and scholars
have been chastised for translating the Western concept of "holy
experience" into scriptures that are mostly prescriptive and performative
rather than informative and experience-oriented. Nonetheless, both contemporary and conventional meditation
discourses are often concerned not only with long-term inner development but
also with the more urgent mental changes that meditation is also believed to
bring about. Even if they are not uniformly present or included in the concept,
such changes in state are prototypical aspects of meditation.
The following list attempts to provide a concise description
of physiological, emotional, and spiritual states that are often associated
with meditation:
• A decrease in arousal.
• Concentration on the mind.
• Emotional sharpness.
• A feeling of being in touch with the most fundamental
facets of life.
The conventional focus on silence, calmness, stillness,
quietude, and tranquilly, as well as contemporary scientific interest in mental
and physical stimulation, are covered in the first point. According to some
researchers, the degree of arousal distinguishes meditative from ecstatic and
shamanic phases, with ecstasy and shamanism suggesting a rise in arousal and
meditation implying a decline.
The theoretical emphasis on transient relaxing of
rationality and preconceived ideas, referred to as "logic
relaxation," in which "ego-related problems and essential assessments
are suspended," also belongs here. The second argument is that meditative
states are correlated with a high level of mental concentration. Absorption
differs from concentration in that it is involuntary rather than active, though
the meanings often correlate, so that Sanskrit dhyana and samadhi, for example,
may refer to both the process of focusing and spontaneous mental absorption,
which may or may not be the result of meditation. Increased attention absorption is often interpreted as
implying less or even no spontaneous thinking movement, also known as mind
wandering. The third point is the subtle perception and attentive presence that
are often associated with meditation. Sleep, drowsiness, or sloth was
considered one of the five barriers to meditative development in Buddhism.
Notice that this type of consciousness and presence is usually accompanied by
satisfaction, as opposed to the caution and watchfulness often associated with
adjectives like "warning" and "wakeful."
This mixture has been dubbed a "wakeful hypometabolic
physiologic condition" in the scientific literature. The fourth argument
is about fleeting encounters that are more directly related to our anxiety
about a person's long-term anchoring in more basic facets of life. The
experiences in question are often couched in metaphorical and strongly
culture-dependent language, referring to a personified god, the self, a way or
path, or more abstract notions such as emptiness or timelessness, or, in Kohn's
definition of meditation, "a deeper, subtler, meditative state." It's debatable whether various accounts of such events refer
to the same ultimate truth, as the perennial view claims, not just because such
representations are always culturally situated, but also because the meanings
themselves are so vague. Also within members of the same group, descriptive
comparisons may mask significant experiential distinctions, varying from subtle
illusions of a transcendent world to drunken hallucinations caused by
psychedelic drugs.
Arousal reduction, in the idealized picture, allows for
mental absorption as thoughts slow down, resulting in increased mental focus
and, eventually, better interaction with essential facets of reality:
- Arousal reduction arousal reduction arousal reduction
arousal reduction
- Absorption of the mind
- Automatic lucidity
- A feeling of being in touch with the most basic facets of
truth
When a person's long-term relationship to himself and his
surroundings is redefined, this sense of touch becomes transformative. The
image's simple simplicity, however, is deceiving, and not only because of the
apparent difficulties in distinguishing the fundamental aspects of truth
described in the fourth point. The first, second, and third points are all
difficult to understand. Regarding the first argument, some cultures associate
meditation with ecstatic states rather than any kind of arousal reduction, and
religious historians have criticized Mircea Eliade's popular distinction
between high-arousal and low-arousal ecstasy.
The exhausting and not especially relaxing experience of
uncertainty is consistently mentioned as a precondition for meditative
development in one Zen Buddhist practice. In terms of the second argument,
efforts to clear the mind of random thoughts have been divisive throughout
meditation's history. Vipayan, also translated as "insight meditation,"
is a distinct category in the Buddhist tradition that covers meditative rituals
that do not strive for mental absorption. The Chinese Zen master Hānshān Déqīng
changed his original emphasis on ridding the mind of thoughts to a focus on
seeing the illusory nature of the thoughts and thus no longer being attached to
them. Furthermore, while current research seems to support the first argument,
namely arousal reduction, the evidence on the second point is much more
ambiguous. On the one hand, seasoned practitioners of breathing
meditation, loving-kindness meditation, and "choiceless
consciousness" showed less mind wandering during meditation in two
scientific trials, and self-reported time on task during breathing meditation
improved in a third study, both appearing to support this claim. Another research,
which asked participants to push a button every time their mind wandered during
meditation, found no distinction between seasoned and beginner meditators, with
mind wandering happening on average every eighty seconds over a twenty-minute
session in both classes.
Some meditation effects have been found to be stronger in
techniques that enable the mind to wander rather than in concentrative
activities. In terms of the third stage, certain western modes of meditation,
such as Transcendental Meditation and Acem Meditation, regard sleep as only one
of many possible states of mind during meditation. Meditation's benefits can
include mental focus, but it's also possible that sleep and drowsiness play a
role. During a visit to a Chinese Zen monastery, I spoke with a monk who
lamented about falling asleep as soon as he began meditating, but added that
after those periods of meditation-induced sleep, his mind became much clearer. Yoga Nidra is a form of lucid sleep that is considered
meditative in the Yoga tradition. To summarize, meditation is not always about
individual mental states, but rather about cycles that can involve a variety of
moods or emotions. As a result, our concept of meditation excludes any
physiological, psychological, or metaphysical states typically associated with
meditative practice. Meditation and Other Meditation Techniques To summarize,
meditation is a method in the sense of a consciously undertaken and structured
process requiring ongoing, i.e., repeated or long-term action aimed at
achieving such outcomes, at least in part, by universal processes.
If the use of attention is marked by a limited concentrative
emphasis or an accessible and inclusive consciousness, it is attention-based.
The expected consequences involve a long-term and profound inner change that
affects several dimensions of a person's life, including perceptual, cognitive,
intellectual, and behavioral habits, as well as a transition toward more
fundamental aspects of nature. In addition, a variety of other traits are often
associated with meditation but do not appear in our description. We've seen how the traditional perception of meditation
includes closed eyes and a sitting stance. In terms of outcomes, we've seen how
meditation is often correlated with short-term changes of state, such as
arousal reduction, mental absorption, mental insight, and a sense of
interaction with basic facets of life. While none of these attributes are
included in our classification, they are all considered to be representative of
meditation.
Meditation, when described in this way, can be
differentiated from a variety of other modes of practice with which it shares
certain characteristics. The borderlines, on the other hand, are always
gradient rather than absolute, and there is a lot of space for overlap. The
following is only a rough sketch of each of these distinctions. Meditation and
pure calming methods are often lumped together in scientific debate. Only
meditation, in our terms, has long-term transformative goals beyond the
wellness and well-being that come with simple stimulation. Methods like radical muscle activation and autogenic
conditioning, with a few exceptions, are not promoted as transformative practices.
In general, contemporary calming methods that rely solely on momentary rest and
leisure are not included in our concept of meditation. Medicine and meditation
are etymologically related, so they may overlap. Meditation is often practiced
for better health in both modern and traditional settings, and inner practices
can be supplemented by medicinal plants, tablets, and concoctions, as in the
Tibetan practices mentioned by Samuel in this volume.
Meditation was once thought to have the ability to drive out
ghosts that might otherwise inflict sickness in early China. However, as Roth
points out in this book, there was no full correlation between meditation and
medicine in early China, and the two were considered different areas. Only when
health-oriented approaches are not used for long-term inner transformation are
they considered meditation in our terms. Prayer, like meditation, is a consciously
practiced activity that often observes more or less well-defined protocols. It always seeks to achieve certain outcomes, such as the
forgiveness of sins, but it can also be inspired by a sense of duty rather than
the expectation of potential benefits. One of the most important differences
between meditation and prayer is the constant practice inherent in the former.
Prayer involves much more nuanced operations, and it often involves sequences
of acts or utterances rather than a single continuous activity; it is linear
rather than continuous. Meditation, unlike prayer, is a technical mode of
self-transformation rather than a communicative way of communicating
commitment, plea, obedience, or gratitude to a spiritual being in the
prototypical example.
In fact, there is a lot of overlap, such as when an orthodox
Christian prays the Jesus Prayer, which is a brief, formulaic, and intensely
devotional prayer that is repeated over and again, often with the help of
breathing exercises. Sufism's dhikr, Hinduism's japa, and Buddhism's niàn-fó,
Chinese, or nen-butsu, Japanese, are all related practices. Devotional visualization
approaches require similar considerations. Many types of meditation, including
prayer, seek to make contact with basic facets of reality, and are often
defined in anthropomorphic terms as supernatural entities with their own sense
of agency. Prayer approaches meditation as it becomes wordless, as in
certain types of Christian mysticism. While the word "mysticism" is
broad and multifaceted, it usually refers to personal perceptions and states
rather than technological concerns. Meditation as a tool for
self-transformation can or may not be associated with a mystical orientation.
Meditation differs from ritual in that it is typically more centered on the
person rather than the group, and it involves continuous or repeated activity
rather than the stepwise or sequential processes of ritual.
Meditation, on the other hand, should be done in a group
environment and ritual in an individual setting. In a number of rituals,
repetition is also an essential component. Meditation is also surrounded by
routine, and practices incorporate meditative components, but the line between
the two is blurry. Shamanism and spirit mediumship include visiting a certain
state of mind and communicating with gods or spirits not for the shaman or
medium's own sake, but for the sake of another person or a group. Though this is not the same as the self-transformative goal
of meditation, many cultures believe that meditation is beneficial not only to
the meditator but also to his surroundings, and group meditation is often
performed for the sake of the whole society. What about bodywork like Hatha
Yoga, Tai Chi, and Qi Gong? These are associated with inner change which
require the use of attention, including the fact that they rely on the body.
They vary from the more common types of meditation in that they contain
sequential rather than repeated movements, in addition to being static and
therefore long-lasting postures.
Traditional martial arts, which are often said to have
meditative aspects, place a greater emphasis on external self-defense than
internal transformation. However, it is arguable that some of them achieve this
aim in part by including strategies for inner change, but, like body rituals,
in a manner that is dependent on sequential rather than repeated motions.
Though it is a transformative technique, psychotherapy varies from meditation
in many ways. For starters, it necessitates the intervention of a
physician, while meditation typically occurs without the constructive or
interfering presence of another entity. Second, psychotherapy scarcely
qualifies as a technique in our narrow context, as it lacks the long-term or
routine characteristics that distinguish meditation. However, different types
of instruction, which are often associated with meditation and are often
considered necessary for its purpose, share these and other psychotherapy
characteristics. There are meditative and non-meditative aspects of certain practices.
Some practitioners pursue long-term improvement, whereas
others seek short-term relaxation; some prioritize inner growth, whereas others
prioritize physical health; some have moral goals, whereas others seek to
enhance their career or athletic results. This pattern isn't limited to western
meditation practices. Traditional meditative techniques can also be used to
attain material prosperity, physical fitness, and other worldly benefits, as
Myrvold and Samuel demonstrate in this book. This review of the essence of
meditation does not address all of the issues surrounding the concept, and we
might still be undecided on whether or not to incorporate specific activities.
In the very least, we have a set of parameters to address.
Many techniques, whether they are called meditation or have
other names, which come close to our meaning but lack one or two
characteristics, putting them in the grey area between meditation and other
forms of practice. Some meditation-like activities, for example, mimic ritual
and prayer except that they are performed in steps rather than in a continuous
or repeated manner. Rather than defining a natural class or taxon, our
description aims to provide a single point of reference for cross-cultural and
comparative research based on functional and theoretical considerations.